Catherine Z. Elgin
Papers on Nelson Goodman
-
Construction and Cognition
(Theoria, 24, 2009, 134-146.)
Abstract:
The Structure of Appearance presents a phenomenalist
system which constructs enduring visible objects out of
qualia. Nevertheless Goodman does not espouse
phenomenalism. Why not? In answering this question this
paper explicates Goodman's views about the nature and
functions of constructional systems, the prospects of
reductionism, and the character of epistemology.
-
Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation
of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
(Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238.)
-
The Legacy of Nelson Goodman
(Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
62, 2001, 679-690.)
Abstract:
Nelson Goodman was one of the foremost philosophers of the twentieth
century. His work radically reshaped the subject, forcing
fundamental reconceptions of philosophy's problems, ends and means.
Goodman not only contributed to diverse fields, from philosophy of
language to aesthetics, from philosophy of science to mereology, his
works cut across these and other fields, revealing shared features
and connecting links that more narrowly focused philosophers
overlook. This paper begins to assess Goodman's legacy by reviewing
his major accomplishments and identifying a cluster of metaphysical,
epistemological, and methodological commitments that run through his
works.
-
Worldmaker: Nelson Goodman
(Journal for General Philosophy of Science,
31, 2000, 1-18.)
-
Reorienting Aesthetics, Reconceiving Cognition
(Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
58, 2000, 219-225.)
-
The Power of Parsimony
(Philosophia Scientiae, 2, 1997, 89-104;
reprinted in Deutsche Zeitschrift für
Philosophie, 45, 1997, 487-499 (in German).)
Abstract:
Extensionalism is often rejected on the grounds that it
cannot explicate metaphor, fiction, indirect discourse, and
ascriptions of propositional attitude. I argue that Nelson
Goodman's extensionalism has the resources to explicate all
these devices. But Goodman recognizes multiple modes of
reference, whereas intensional theories recognize only
one. So it is not obvious that his theory is more austere
than its intensional rivals. What recommends Goodman's
extensionalism, I contend, is not its ontological austerity
so much as its flexibility and sensitivity to context.
-
What Goodman Leaves Out
(Journal of Aesthetic Education,
25, 1991, 89-96.)
-
Changing the Subject, with Nelson Goodman,
(The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
46, 1987, 219-233; reprinted in Analytic Aesthetics,
ed. Richard Shusterman, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989, 190-196;
and in Estetyka w swiecie, ed. Maria Golaszewska
(in Polish).)
Abstract:
We argue that the analytic turn enabled aesthetics to shift
its focus to the study of symbols. With this reconception, a
variety of traditional aesthetic problems, such as the
paradox of ugliness, dissolve; others, including the role of
emotion and the importance of excellence, are
reconceived. This enables us to see how arts function
cognitively -- how they contribute, when effective, to human
understanding.